The Right to Abortion and the European Convention on Human Rights
In Search of Consensus among Member-States
Abortion bans are back in Vogue! Nearly 165 years after the first massive demonstration on women’s rights, discussions on the extent to which interference with female bodies falls within States’ margin of appreciation (‘MoA’) remain apropos. Indeed, the recent Polish near-absolute abortion ban has revived the debate on the existence of a foetus’ right to life and balancing it with women’s right to abortion.
Against this background, the present post sheds light on the status of the ‘right to abortion’ in international law. To this end, it explores the status of this putative right through the lenses of the relevant jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights (‘ECtHR’) and other regional bodies as well as of the customary interpretative tools enshrined in the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (‘VCLT’).
A Foetus’ “Right to Life” v. A Woman’s “Right to Abortion”
The ECtHR Grand Chamber most explicitly stated its position on the foetus’ right to life in its famous Vo v. France judgment. Precisely, it highlighted that the unborn is not regarded as a “person” directly protected under the European Convention on Human Rights (‘ECHR’) Article 2 and that ‘if the unborn do have a “right” to “life”, it is implicitly limited by the mother’s rights and interests’ (para 80). It further noted that the ECHR institutions have not ‘ruled out the possibility that in certain circumstances safeguards may be extended to the unborn child’ (Vo v. France, para 80). In this passage, the Court seems to have distinguished between the right to life on one hand and safeguards that may, under certain circumstances, be extended to the unborn on the other; the ECtHR does not regard the unborn as a holder of the right to life but rather as a beneficiary of some safeguards under certain circumstances.
On the existence of a right to abortion, the Court underlined – just as the Commission already had (Brüggemann and Scheuten v. Germany, para 61) – that, although legislation regulating the interruption of pregnancy touches upon the sphere of private life, protected by ECHR Article 8(1), the norm ‘cannot be interpreted as meaning that pregnancy and its termination are, as a principle, solely a matter of the private life of the mother’ (Vo v. France, para 80). Instead, ‘the issue’ is ‘determined by weighing up various, and sometimes conflicting, rights or freedoms claimed by a woman, a mother or a father in relation to one another or vis-à-vis an unborn child.’ (Vo v. France, para 80). The Court has clarified that when the pregnant woman’s life is risked, access to abortion is non-negotiable (X v. the United Kingdom, para 19).
In 2010, it further acknowledged a consensus amongst the substantial majority of ECHR States-parties towards allowing abortion on broader grounds than the risk to the pregnant woman’s health (A, B and C v. Ireland, para 235). However, it found that the MoA enjoyed by the States on the regulation of abortions remained broad and that allowing abortions only when the health of the mother is at stake, did not exceed this MoA (A, B and C v. Ireland, para 241). To reach this conclusion, the Court relied on applicants’ discretion to travel to other ECHR States-parties for the requested abortion.
Overview of ECHR Member-States’ Current Approach
Eleven years later, out of the 47 ECHR States-parties, 40 do not only acknowledge the legality of abortion on broader grounds, but have further legalised abortion on demand during the first 10 to 24 weeks of the pregnancy.
Conversely, 7 ECHR Member-States maintain strict anti-abortion policies, ranging from Malta and Andorra prohibiting abortions in all circumstances [a deviation from the existing case-law of ECHR-institutions on the matter (X v. the United Kingdom, para 19)] to San Marino and Liechtenstein, which allow abortions when the pregnancy poses a serious danger to the woman’s life or health, or results from rape or sexual assault. In Monaco and Hungary abortions are additionally allowed in cases of fetal deformity, whereas in Poland – although prohibited in case of fetal deformity – abortions are legal in cases of incest, rape, or when the pregnancy threatens the life of the mother.
These States send an explicit message of differentiated practice among ECHR Member States. Such practice of the ECHR does not qualify as an interpretative tool under VCLT Article 31(3)(b) (Villiger, pp. 431-432), which envisages a uniform subsequent state practice (or at least a convergent practice of the majority of States-parties, to which the other States-parties assent or do not oppose). This was most likely the basis of ECtHR’s pronouncement of a wide MoA enjoyed by the States on the regulation of abortions.
Towards a Holistic Interpretation of the ECHR
Still, the practice described can – and should – be taken into account as a supplementary tool of interpretation in a holistic appraisal of the ECHR [in line with VCLT Article 32]. In fact, against the background of the principle ex injuria, jus non oritur, according to which illegal acts do not create law and which can also serve as an interpretative tool (Pellet, pp. 7-9), the interpretative value of unlawful absolute anti-abortion state practices (i.e. of Malta and Andorra) decreases vis-à-vis the lawful practice of other ECHR-parties.
Furthermore, for the interpretation of ECHR Article 8 and the identification of the scope of the right to abortion entailed therein, inspiration may be drawn from relevant rules of international law [VCLT Article 31(3)(c)]. In this regard, the Human Rights Committee (‘HRCtee’) has repeatedly (Zureick, pp. 125-130) underlined that regulations restricting a woman’s access to abortion in cases of rape or incest are incompatible with Article 7 (freedom from torture or cruel, inhuman or degrading behaviour) of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (“ICCPR”). Similarly, the Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination Against Women has called for States to allow abortion beyond cases where pregnancy threatens a woman’s life. Likewise, the HRCtee clarified that restrictions on access to abortion in cases of fatal foetal abnormality violate inter alia Article 7 of the ICCPR and that the ability of pregnant women to travel abroad in order to obtain the required abortion did not purify such violation (Mellet v. Ireland, para. 9; Whelan v. Ireland, para. 9). In a similar fashion, the Inter-American Commission on Human Rights (‘IACHR’) has persistently urged States to safeguard women’s reproductive rights. In fact, in a Joint Statement with human rights experts, the IACHR’s Rapporteur on the Rights of Women called on States to legalise abortions – at the very minimum – in cases of sexual assault, rape, incest, and where the continued pregnancy endangers a woman’s mental and physical health.
Against this background, seeing the ECtHR acknowledge that a Member-State does not violate its ECHR obligations simply because another ECHR Member-State steps in and assures the protection of women’s access to abortion seems rather obscure. However, this is the approach the Court has so far embraced (A, B and C v. Ireland, para. 239) and maintained, despite criticism (Ghráinne and McMahon, 569).
After all, the ECtHR’s consideration of predominant moral perceptions in one State (A, B and C v. Ireland, para. 239) does not align with a contextual and evolutive interpretation of the ECHR. Precisely, it has been argued that, as during the drafting of the ECHR, abortion was illegal in most States, the intention of the drafters could not have been to grant a right to abortion, especially a right to abortion on demand. Aside from the flawed perception of human rights as derivative rights, inherent in this argumentation, the latter neglects the intention of the drafters to create a document adaptable to the times (Tyrer v. the United Kingdom, para 31). In fact, protests on the legalisation of abortion on demand indicate a changing moral perception of abortion, buttressed by the practice of a majority of ECHR-parties.
Against this background, it seems that it is about time that the so far unspoken right to abortion found its way into the ECtHR’s jurisprudence!
I mentioned I will write another post. The topic in question is more appropriate for two another blog posts so I’ll continue that discussion there. The two blog posts in question are:
Is the Feministisation of the ECtHR’s Abortion-Related Jurisprudence a Realistic Expectation?
Towards a Feminist Interpretation of the ECHR’s Provisions on Access to Abortion
In one of my previous posts I mentioned four questions. Since Katsoni didn’t want to answer them I’ll give short answers to those questions.
1. The Court excludes the unborn person from the scope of the Convention?
The answeris no. The Court has never excluded the unborn child from the scope of the convention. This is explained in previous posts in detail.
2. Access to abortion on demand can be claimed based on the Convention?
It can’t. The Court was explicit on the fact that there is no right to abortion. Case law is quoted in my previous posts.
3. The refusal to grant access to abortion on demand infringes a right guaranteed by the Convention?
Same answer as to the previous question. Also, EVEN IF the Court would say that the unborn child is not a person, abortion would till not be a human right. The Court has already recognized that “pregnancy cannot be said to pertain uniquely to the sphere of private life”(Bruggemann & Scheuten v. Germany). In Boso v. Italy and X v. UK the Court has acknowledged that the “potential fathers” were victims of the abortion, but that the abortion was justified by medical indications. (This is an example of “double effect” principle). And how the proportionality test should have been different in case of abortion on demand.
Also worth mentioning, legitimate interest of society to limit the number of abortions. (Odievre v. France).
The interests of society in relation to the protection of morals. (Open Door & Dublin Well Woman v. Ireland).
And many others.
4. The practice of abortion on demand does not curtail any right and interest guaranteed by the Convention?
As you can see from my previous answer, you cannot claim that even if the Court would say that unborn child is not a person. Other way around if the Court says the unborn child is a person, that means an immediate ban on abortion and only the principle of “double effect” would be applicable. For now it is “not desirable”(quoting the Court) for the Court to answer that question; everyone can judge that for themselves, just be careful not to be on the wrong side of history like some were in times of slavery. Fortunately slavary was abolished. Can you define who humans(persons) are in a way to exclude the unborn and not to exclude any of the born in the process? Good luck with that.
I’ll write another post soon about Ireland and their legalization of abortion as it is a good example of how various legitimate interests mentioned come into play.
In this post let me mention the UN Committee on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities. I’ll quote them and I think it will be easy to find the official document:
“Laws which explicitly allow for abortion on grounds of impairment violate the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (Art,. 4,5,8)”
This Committee further explained that this type of abortion is often based on inaccurate diagnosis and that “even if it is not false, the assessment perpetuates notions of stereotyping disability as incompatible with a good life”.
Katsoni mentions and quotes bodies like CEDAW in her article and at same time CRPD she does not even mention. It is well known that there is no article in CEDAW that even remotely mentions abortion and their decisions are not binding to the States. CEDAW Committee is substantially composed of abortion activists and many of them have publicly taken a stand in favor on abortion. Their claims are besed on a broken record called “let’s make up new rights because…living instrument… who cares what the Court says”, imagine that. Connection of some CEDAW members with various pro abortion NGOs is well known and their strategic litigation strategy has been same for years.
Recently, ECLJ has made two reports one is exposing the impartiality of ECHR judges and their conflicts of interests. The other report exposes the “dark funding” of the so called “UN experts” and how they influence human rights. Those reports have been acknowledged worldwide.
In case someone is reading this there are few more points to discuss. Katsoni states how “the practice described should be taken as a supplementary tool of interpretation in line with VCLT article 32”. An obvious question needs to be asked. Why is that so?
Article 31 is the primary rule of interpretation, article 32 is supplementary used only in addition to article 31 under certain circumstances which do not apply here. You can not just skip article 31 and go on your merry way to article 32. It is not applicable here because the case law of the Corut is clear (there is no right to abortion) not to mention Katsoni also using “evolutive interpretation” when the Court is clear it can not be used to create new rights.
I mention it as this is a common trick among abortion activists; i.e. blatantly ignoring case law and using instruments like “evolutive interpretation” and “living instrument” for things they are not meant to be used, like creating new rights.
Katsoni mentions the correct interpretation in her article but she calls it a “flawed perception of human rights…and neglecting the evelutive interpretation…”.
VCLT article 31 states: 1. “A treaty shall be interpreted in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given
to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of its object and purpose.”
This is a lengthy topic but the context is very clear. UDHR from which ECHR is derived was made because of the experience of World War II, that’s where you get the context, object and purpose from.
The Europen Court of HUMAN Rights claims(*) that it does not know who HUMANS(persons) are. In this context saying that abortion is a human right would lead to a result that is “manifestly absurd and unreasonable”, like it’s mentioned in the VCLT. The Court is very clear in it’s reasoning when applaying the principle of “double effect” under specific circumstances and saying “EVEN IF unborn child is a person…”, excluding all other circumstances like abortion on demand in the process. Imagine the European Court of HUMAN rights saying: “EVEN if unborn child is a person, you are allowed to kill it”.
In recent history, not so long ago, slavery was legal and slaves were not persons. But imagine that, today they are persons. Do you really want to be wrong again?
(*) That claim is pretty absurd in itself as the whole purpose of “HUMAN(person) rights” is to actually protect HUMANS(persons). You can not do that while at same time claiming “I don’t know who HUMANS(persons) are” and “it is not desireable to answer that question”. That’s what the Court is doing at this very moment. On the other hand, American Convention of Humna Right is clear, HUMANS are PERSONS from conception.
This comment is an addition to my two posts made few days ago. (two posts ae not yet visible) In the conclusion of her article Katsoni states that “the latter neglects the intention of the drafters to create a document adaptable to the times”. This is what is known as “living instrument” or “evolutive interpretation”. And from it she tries to derive the so called “unspoken right to abortion”.
In my previous comments I have already quoted case law of the Court and as a matter of fact the Court has already established that there is no right to abortion and no right to practice it. (see previous comments for the cases)
Further, the interpretative power of the court is limited and the Court cannot create a right not included in the convention. Please see Johnston & others v. Ireland and Emonet & others v. Switzerland.
To quote the Court: “the Convention and its Protocols must be interpreted in the light of present-day conditions. However, the Court cannot, by means of evolutive interpretation, derive from these instruments a right that was not included at the outset. This is particularly so here, when the omission was deliberate”
So under no circumstances, not even interpreting the Convention in evolutive manner can the Court create a new right not included in the convention.
Therefore, the conclusion of this article is flawed and the case law confirms it. Because the conclusion of this article does exactly what the Court said cannot be done, it tries to derive by means of evolutive interpretation a non existing “right to abortion”.
In the last paragraph of the article the author talkes of how the “unspoken right to abortion” should find it’s way into the courts juresprudence. It’s already mentioned in my previous comments examining the case law of the Court and how the Corut already has explicitly stated that abortion in not a right under the Convention.
Because of the clear misinterpretations of Vo v. France and obvious cherry picking case law a question of this articles authors bias should be raised. The topc is obviously seen one sided and poorly researched by the author.
The authors claims of “unspoken right to abortion” is made based on Courts instruments of “evolutive interpretation” and so called “european consensus”. Worth mentioning is that the “consensus” argument has already failed in A.B.C v. Ireland case. And how “evolutive interpretation” or “living instrument” is not meant to introduce new rights which are not recognized by the convention and cannot stem from it.
New rights can be introduced by way of adoption of “optional protocols” by state parties. While it’s true that the majority of member stares allow abortion on demand under some restrictions, there is no consensus “stricto sensu”. In fact, most member states constututions protect right of life of the unborn. Most notable example is Germany (see Annen v. Germany) as under German constitution by interpretation of german constitutional court abortion is an “act of killing” and illegal under the german law but not punishable during the first 12 weeks of pregnancy.
Regarding the authors statement of “changing moral perception” and linking an article talking about protests in Poland. That article talks about protests againt a recent ban on “eugenic abortions”. Most of those abortions are performen on unborn children with Down sindrome. What’s the moral perception here on eugenic abortions? If it’s ok to abort the unborn with Down syndrome is it also ok to abort based on sex or race of the unborn child?
Since the author talkes about “changing moral perception” why give an example of specific country and protests against specific ban on eugenic abortions. You could have mentioned the pro life “One of Us” European Citizen Initiative(ECI) which had brought together the largest number of signatures in the history of Europe.
Visiting this article today I can see that the false statement has not been retracted. In my previous comments this articles author’s misintrerpretation of para 80 of Vo v. France have been explained in more detail. In short the author of this article falsely clames how ECHR does not regard the unborn as a person under the Convention.
The author bases her claims on Vo v. France para 80 which she misinterpretes and simply drops “in the circumstances examined to date”. Even Vo v France refutes her conclusions. Para 75 clearly states how “the Court has yet to determine the issue” and para 85 clearly states that under the circumstances of the instant case the Court “considers it unnecessary to examine” the issue.
So, according to the claims of the Court in Vo v. France, the issue has not been settlet in prior case law (para 75), and it has not been examined in Vo v France (para 85). Thus it can not be claimed based on Vo v. France that the issue has been settled like the author of this article does. Which makes it obvious that the author of this article makes a flase claim misintrepreting article 80 and conveniently drpping an esential part.
“in the circumstances examined to date” is the essencial part. If you look closely para 75 mentions X v. U.K. and para 80 mentions Boso v. Italy. In those cases when the “life or health” of the mother are in danger then “even if one assumes” unborn is a person(human) then under those circumstances “the abortion is covered by an implied limitation, protecting the life and health of the woman”. That’s what’s called the principle of “double effect” in my previous comments. And this has nothing to do with other circumstances like abortion on demand.
Furthe the author of this article claims she “does not believe” the 4 questions should be answered by her to defend her position. Her position being based on secondary issues of “consensus” and “living instrument” by which she introduces non existing “right to abortion”. It was shown in previous comments that by Courts case law and that the court explicitly stated there is no right to abortion under the convention.
To simplify what the author claims by this, she claims that it should be allowed to intentionally kill another person(human) just by the will of the mother. This is simply false since the principle of “sanctity of life” is protected under the Convention. See Reeve v. U.K. and Streletz, Kessler & Krenz v. Germany. The court confirms that “the right to life is an inalienable attribute of the human beings and forms the supreme value in the hierarchy of human rights”.
Thus, no, intentional killing of another person(human) is not allowed. And the question is still not settled in the context of abortion since the European Court of HUMAN Righs does not know who is and who isn’t human(person). That’s why we have MoA, but same as secondary issues of “consensus” and “living instrument” once the issue is settled MoA is irrelevant. So certainly if you want to defend your position the primary issue should be addressed.
Dear Sissy Katsoni.
Thanks for another reply. I still fail to see what you disagree on as you have not addressed the primary issues I have mentioned, not to mention the four points. Your argumentation is based on the secondary issues, thus flawed, and somehow you manage to pull the non existant “right to abortion” from it.
The Court has explicitly declared that abortion is not a right under the Convention; there is no right to have an abortion (Silva Monteiro Martins Ribeiro v. Portugal) and there is no right to practice it (Jean-Jacques Amy v. Belgium). Not to mentioned the two applicants that unsuccessfully complained on the prohibition of abortion on demand in A.B.C. v. Ireland.
To quote you “Against this background, it seems that it is about time that the so far unspoken right to abortion found its way into the ECtHR’s jurisprudence!”. Unspoken? The right is obviously non existant from the Courts jurisprudence, as it’s clear from the above mentioned cases.
The above should address some of the obvious points. And I fail to see on what bases you disagree since you’re still insisting on the secondary issues which are not essencial.
As you say, “from your viewpoint” that the Courts juresprudence “suggests that it does not equate foetus to persons” and then you continue with “the foetus is rather seen as a potential beneficiary of safeguards under certain circumstances.” When it is clear in fact that the Court has never stated that the unborn child is not a person.
What is clear from the above “viewpoint” of yours is that you do not understand the margin of appreciation or how it is used by the Court. Please see A.B.C v. Ireland, R.R. v. Poland, P. and S. v. Poland, Tysiac v. Poland. The court has many times emphesised that “once the state, acting within its limits of appreciation, adopts statutory regulations allowing abortion in some situations” then “the legal framework devised for this purpose should be shaped in a coherent manner which allows the different legitimate interests involved to be taken into account adequately and in accordance with the obligations deriving from the Convention”. Once the member State allows abortion it’s “margin of appreciantion is not unlimited as to how it balances the conflicting rights” and “the Court must supervise whether the interference constitutes a proportionate balancing of the competing interests involved” (A.B.C. v. Ireland).
The above has been the principle of how the Court regulates abortion. To emphasize again the fact that, the Court has never concluded that the unborn child is not a person. Not even in Vo v. France if you missed the para. 85.
Your viewpoint is thus flawed as you’re concetrating on the secondary issuses which fall under the context of “once the state” allows abortion in some circumstances. And this is where the balancing of various conflicting rights and freedoms kicks in as the MoA is not unlimited. And since MoA is not unlimited the unborn child is still “potential beneficiary of safeguards under certain circumstances”, to quote you.
Like you said in your article “However, it found that the MoA enjoyed by the States on the regulation of abortions remained broad and that allowing abortions only when the health of the mother is at stake, did not exceed this MoA”. It is thus as easy for a State to protect the life of the unborn child from fertilizastion. There is nothing to “balance” in this case as the mother and the child have the same rights as both are regarded as “persons” and the principle of “double effect” applies.
We can not “agree to disagree” as long as you are concetrating on the secondary issues and avoiding to address the primary. Not to mention cherry picking case law to avoid the fact that the Court has already explicitly declared that abortion is not a right under the Convention.
Dear Patrick M.,
I understand that for you an answer on whether the foetus is a person is a primary one. For me it is not. For the reasons I have mentioned above, and in the comment section, I do not believe that it has the same rights as a bearing person. The court has after all stated that ‘if the unborn do have a “right” to “life”, it is implicitly limited by the mother’s rights and interests’ (Vo v France, para 80). Furthermore, I do not believe that the questions/4 points you raised shall be answered for me to ‘defend my position’. I feel that the above analysis suffices for an alternative approach/interpretative outcome to be defended.
Regarding the margin of appreciation issue in A B and C, I would highly recommend the blogpost published on the Strasbourg observers on this judgement. Perhaps, it can further help you understand the approach argued here and in other academic writings.
Finally, I am afraid that regardless of whether you feel like agreeing to disagree, we will have to end a futile discussion at some point. It has, by now, turnt into a mere reiteration of the same arguments by both sides. With so many pending applications against Poland, we will soon receive answers by the Court itself. In the meantime, I wish you all the best with your research endeavours.
Best,
Sissy
Dear Sissy Katsoni.
Let me quote your article “The ECtHR Grand Chamber most explicitly stated its position on the foetus’ right to life in its famous Vo v. France judgment. Precisely, it highlighted that the unborn is not regarded as a “person” directly protected under the European Convention on Human Rights (‘ECHR’) Article 2”.
There you state explicitly a much stronger claim that the Court declared that the unborn is not regarded as a person. In the comments you weakened your claim with therms like “in my view”, “i believe”, etc…
You have somehow conveniently managed to drop the “in the circumstances examined to date” in you article. Further para 75. explicitly states “The Court has yet to determine the issue of the “beginning” of “everyone’s right to life” within the meaning of this provision and whether the unborn child has such a right.”. And para 85. states that “As to the instant case, it considers it unnecessary to examine whether the abrupt end to the applicant’s pregnancy falls within the scope of Article 2”. Also how it is not “desireable” or possible to “determine” if the unborn child is a “person”.
Thus it’s pretty clear that your statement is not correct. The Court has never said that the unborn child is not a person.
To quote you again: “I understand that for you an answer on whether the foetus is a person is a primary one. For me it’s not. For reasons that I have mentioned above and in the comment section, I do not believe that it has the same right as a bearing person.”
Are we still dicussing the fact that the Court did not ever conclude that the unborn child is not a person. Or are you trying to shift the topic to what you believe a person is or is not? That is a different topic entirely. What you believe or not believe personally does not in any way defend your false statement in the article.
For the Court the question of the status of unborn child, whether it is a person is primary. That’s why we have the MoA.
To quote you: “The Court has after all stated that ‘if the unborn do have a “right” to “life”, it is implicitly limited by the mother’s rights and interests’”. That is correct, if both mother and unborn child are persons they have equal rights including right to life. Then the principle of “double effect” applies. I doubt any reasonable person would claim differently, that is to claim that intentional killing or another person is allowed, especially in cases such as “abortion on demand” just because the mother desires so. Even less that it is a human right.
Dear Patrick M.,
Thank you very much for your comment.
In the above article, I have highlighted that the court, after recapitulating the jurisprudence of the ECHR instituttions, noted that ‘the unborn child is not regarded as a “person” directly protected by Article 2 of the Convention and that if the unborn do have a “right” to “life”, it is implicitly limited by the mother’s rights and interests. The Convention institutions have not, however, ruled out the possibility that in certain circumstances safeguards may be extended to the unborn child’ (Vo v. France, para 80). I further underlined the terminology used by the Court here. The Court does not refer to any safeguards of the foetus as a person’s rights. It mentions that in certain circumstances safeguards may be extended to the unborn child. Thus, from my viewpoint the Court does not equate a foetus with a person and rights’ holder, not only because it deems the former as an entity, to which safeguards – and not rights – may be in certain circumstances extended, but also because it indicates a perception of the foetus as an entity, which is not a holder of direct rights, as is the case with persons. The foetus’ safeguards are only extended to it.
At any rate, regardless the question on the foetus’ status and safeguards, I argue above that the Court should have adopted a much broader interpretation of the right to abortion, which would be in line with VCLT. I would further like to bring to your attention the dissenting opinions of Judge Rozakis, Tulkens, Fura, Hirvelä, Malinverni and Poalelungi, as well as the concurring opinion on Judge Finlay Geoghegan in A B and C v. Ireland, who highlight that a broad consensus has been reached among ECHR parties on abortion on demand and, thus, that the margin of appreciation on the matter should be seen as narrow.
I hope that the above answer clarifies my argumentation in this article.
Kind regards,
Sissy Katsoni
Dear Sissy Katsoni.
I have also put an emphasis oh the “circumstances examined to date” as abortion on demand is a blind spot in case law at the Court. You have simply restated your previous position ignoring the elephant in the room. What is clear from Vo v. France is that the Court does not know who is or who isn’t a person or human. Thus, the status of the unborn child is not resolved. The Court stated itself that it is not “desireable” or “possible” to do so.
Regarding your mention of concurring opinion in A.B.C. v. Ireland and how the “margin of appreciation” should be narrow. The abortion cases against Poland and Ireland clearly show that there is no right to abortion. And it is clear that every member state has te posibility to restrict access to abortion as for example Poland does today or to allow abortion on demand as many stated to. The margin is clearly pretty wide.
Since you mention VCLT I’ll mention that Article 31 states: “A treaty shall be interpreted in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of its object and purpose.” And the fact that at the time the Convention was drafted there was a broad consensus on the criminal nature of “abortion on demand”. And the Court itself has never excluded prenatal life from it’s field of allpication. As President Jean-Paul Costa explained in his separate opinion under Vo v. France: “Had the article 2 been considered to be entirely inapplicable, there would have been no point and this applies to the present case also – in examining the question of foetal protection and the possible violation of Article 2, or in using this reasoning to find that there had been no violation of that provision.”
The issues of “european consensus”, “margin of appreciation” and “living instrument” are important but secondary. And greater care should be made when examining case law. Primary issue is on the status of the unborn child and it’s seems to the Court it is not “desireable” or “possible” to determine who is and how isn’t a “person”.
Since your argumentation is flawed. I recommend an article on Ejil Talk titled “In Defence of a More Sophisticated and Nuanced Approach To Abortion: A Response to Gregor Puppinck”. You’re making the same mistake as the authors of the article concentrating on the secondary issues. As stated there in comments, if you really want to defend your position you should demonstrate that:
1. the Court excludes the unborn person from the scope of the Convention;
2. access to abortion on demand can be claimed based on the Convention;
3. the refusal to grant access to abortion on demand infringes a right guaranteed by the Convention;
4. the practice of abortion on demand does not curtail any right and interest guaranteed by the Convention.
Seems even the authors of the mentioned article have failed to demonstrate that to date.
Dear Patrick M.,
I cannot help but disagree with most points stated in your comment.
First of all, the Court has indeed avoided ruling on whether the foetus falls within the personal scope of the right to life. From my viewpoint, however, the indications that the Court has provided in its jurisprudence seem to suggest that it does not equate the foetus to persons (e.g. the bearing person). The foetus is rather seen as a potential beneficiary of safeguards under certain circumstances. I believe that the reference to the ‘circumstances examined to date’ does not affect this conclusion, and if it did, States’ practice would have to be taken into consideration. This state practice shows that abortion on demand is allowed during several weeks of the pregnancy and that the state practice allowing abortion on demand is growing. Thus, from my viewpoint, this would verify the initial indication that the ECtHR does not perceive foetus as a person.
Secondly, regarding the hierarchy among the tools of treaty interpretation, to which you refer in your comment, I am of the view that a holistic interpretation of treaties is always more favourable [on the lack of hierarchy among all VCLT Art 31 paragraphs, see: E Methymaki and A Tzanakopoulos, ‘Masters of Puppets? Reassertion of Control through Joint – Investment Treaty Interpretation’ in Kulick (ed.), Reassertion of Control over the Investment Treaty Regime (CUP 2016) 169]. After all, just as a right to abortion is not explicitly mentioned in the ECHR, a right to a healthy environment is also not included, and not thought of during the drafting of the treaty, etc. Nevertheless, the jurisprudence of the ECtHR has developed its in environmental matters on account of the fact that the exercise of certain Convention rights may be undermined by the existence of harm to the environment and exposure to environmental risks. And it seems that it will continue to do so… I believe that the same is done in abortion cases and hope that the Court will continue doing so.
For these reasons I agree with the post on EJIL:Talk!, which you reference in your comment, and I grossly disagree with your comment and Gregor Pupnick’s relevant analysis. I guess we can conclude with an ‘agree to disagree’ epilogue.
All the best,
Sissy Katsoni
Owing to the very substance of the act, killing an innocent human being can never become a “right”, even if – which unfortunately never can be excluded – a prestigious institution like the ECtHR should commit the tragic error of “recognising” it as such. And it is also a tragic error of the author of this piece that she seems to be striving for a political “victory” in court that would actually be nothing but a defeat of humanity.
The ECtHR in fact has abdicated its role as a protector of human rights when, precisely in Vo v. France, it first transformed “human rights” into “person rights”, and then made the claim that “it is neither possible nor desirable” to determine who is, and who isn’t, a “person”. Of course, there can be no serious doubt among educated people that the human embryo is a human being – he is, after all, not a dog, or a cat, or a bonsai tree. As long as human rights are what their name suggests they are, the human embryo is a holder of human rights. Abortion, far from being a human right, is very obviously a human rights violation.
This changes when, as in Vo, the concept of “human rights” is substituted by “person rights”. While the question of the qualification of the embryo as a human being is, as the Court recognises, essentially an objective scientific question to which we all know the answer, the new idea of re-branding human rights as “person rights” opens up the way towards unfettered subjectivism. That precisely appears to be the purpose. Where everybody has the right to define the concept of “person” however he sees fit, it is indeed going to be “impossible” to identify common ground. But by saying that that it is “not desirable” to answer the question whether the embryo is a “person”, the Court has let its mask slip: here we are in the presence of a judicial institution that is not seeking, but fleeing, insight, lest that insight would lead to an outcome that might be unpopular in certain quarters. One cannot take such a court seriously, one can only regret the power and prestige it (still) enjoys…
Dear Mr. Cornides,
Thank you very much for your comment.
Firstly, I would like to draw your attention to Vo v. France para. 80, where the Court, summarising the Convention’s institutions findings in previous decisions, explicitly notes that ‘the unborn child is not regarded as a “person” directly protected by Article 2 of the Convention’. Furthermore, as I understand from your comment, you have seen the Vo. judgement as suggesting a differentiation between “human rights” on one hand and “persons’ rights” on the other. However, such a differentiation is not reflected in the jurisprudence of the ECtHR, which uses the terms “person” and “individual” and “persons’ rights” and “human rights” as synonyms (indicatively Tyrer v. the U.K, para. 33).
On the contrary, in the Vo. judgement, the Court makes a differentiation between a person’s human rights on one hand and the safeguards that may – under certain circumstances – be extended to the unborn child on the other (Vo. v France, para. 80). Against this background, it becomes clear that the ECtHR does not regard the unborn as a holder of the right to life but rather as a beneficiary of some safeguards under certain circumstances.
Finally, on a metalegal note, which seems to be running through your comment as well, I would like to underline that fully acknowledging females’ right of physical integrity (a right which inheres in every individual and can therefore only be acknowledged by human rights instruments and fora and not granted thereby) will not defeat humanity but it will rather help render humanity (more) humane.
Kind regards,
Spyridoula Katsoni
Dear Mr. Katsoni,
Vo v. France para. 80 does not state the thing you claim it does. What it states is “that in the circumstances examined to date by the Convention institutions”…
Emphasis on “circumstances” examined to date. As a matter of fact ECHR has never excluded the unborn person from the scope of the Convention. Abortion on demand is a “blind spot” in case law and the Court has never concluded that it does not violate the Convetion. Thus the member states are given a wide “margin of appreciation” enabling them to regulate abortion.
Given your statement as in Tryer v. U.K. about ECHR regarding “person rights” and “human rights” as synonyms taken together with the Courts own claim that it is “neither possible nor desireable” to determine who is and who isn’t a “person”. I hope you see the elephant in the room?
The “European Court of HUMAN Rights” does not know who is and who isn’t HUMAN and it’s not desireable or possible to determine that?